Jain Friends Home Books Index Articles Index
Jain Friends |
JAINA
EPISTEMOLOGY 1-Pratyaksa
Pramana (Direct Knowledge) Logical
discussions Epistemology
evolved as a result of logical discussions. Such discussions and debates
as the sceptics and sophists engaged in, in ancient Greece, were
prevalent in Ancient India. They aimed at defending their own theories
while refuting those of their opponents. The
Sutta Nipata, which is
supposed to be one of the earliest parts of the Pali Scripture, states
that such debates took place among the Sramanas1
and Brahamanas2. Sometimes
the Titthiyas (including
Ajivikas and Niganthas)3, the so called Vadasilas
(habituate in the debate), have also been associated with these
debates.4 All
these debates are named takki5
or takkika.6 In Pali
literature the ten possible ways of claiming knowledge have been
criticised by the Buddha in addressing Kalama.7 One of them is called
"takka-hetu" which
has been explained in the Commentary as "takka-gahena"
(addhering to reason)8. This takki-hetu appears to be closely realated
to pramana or epistemological
or logical ground, which is perhaps used first by Umasvami, Jaina Acarya
of about the 1st century A.D.9 The word hetu
is also referred to in this sense in the Bhagwati
Sutra (336) and the Thanangasutra
(309-10). Such
discussions were held for the sake of gaining triumph in arguments or to
defend religions. The debaters used the vada,
jalpa and vitanda forms
which are teh classifications of katha
or discussion in the Nyaya tradition. Pali literature also makes similar
references to this classification. The Sutta
Nipata mentions the vada12,
katha13 and vitanda.14
Buddhaghose associates this vitandasattha
with the Brahmanas, while the Saddaniti
refers to the Titthiyas. It shows the vitanda
was utilized at that time by all schools of thought, since the term Titthiya
was applied to both the samanas and the Brahamanas. The
discussion through which knowledge is gained about doctrines is called
the Vada; that which is only
for gaining victory over the opponents is Jalpa;
the debate where the quibbles (chala)
analogues (jati) and
respondent's failures (nigrahasthana)
are utilized to vanquish the opponent is called vitanda
in Nyaya system and was used to defend their own views by right or wrong
means.15 The
Buddhist tradition also could not escape being influenced by this
practice. The old logical compenda like the Upayahrdaya,
Tarkasastra, etc. appear to have allowed the use of quibbles
analogues etc. for the specific purpose of protecting the Buddhist
order, but Dharmakirti, realising that it was not in keeping with the
high standards of truth and non-violence, completely denied their usage
in the Vadanyaya. Hence,
Dharmakirti refers the qualities of the debater who speaks more or less
than necessary. Therefore he acepts only the two Nigrahasthanas,
Asadhananga and Adosodbhavana
for vadi as well as prativadi.16 The
Jainas, on the other hand, lay more stress on truth and non-violence.
They think of the Vitanda as Vitandabhasa.17
Akalanka rejects even the Asadhananga
and Adosodbhavana in view of
the fact that they are themselves the subjects of discussion. He then
says: a defendant should himself indicate the real defects in the
established theory of a disputant and then set up his own theory.18 Thus
he should consider each item from the point of view of truth and
non-violence. The
above fact is supported by Pali literature which contains references to
the logical discussions of that period. Some adherents of Jainism had
also participated in such discussions. Saccaka, Abhaya and
Asibandhakaputta Gamini are the main characters who took an active part
in them. Saccaka
is described in the Nikayas
as one who indulged in debate, a learned, controversialist, who was
highly esteemed by the common people.19 He is said to have debated with
all the six teachers, including even Mahavira (Nigantha Nataputta),
although Saccaka was a staunch follower of Nigantha Nataputta. This may
imply that he was a follower of the Parsvanatha tradition. But as
Nigantha Nataputta became a Tirthankara of Jainism, Saccaka would have
examined him through discussions and then accepted his religion, which
was nothing but the refarmation of the Parsvanatha tradition. Saccaka
boasts about his dialaectical skillin magniloquent language and speaks
to the Licchavis at Vaisali: "To-day there will be a conversation
between me and recluse Gautama. If Gautam takes up his stand against me,
even as a powerful man, having taken hold of the fleece of a long
fleeced ram, might tug it towards him," Further it has been
mentioned there that the Buddha had asked a question which could not be
replied by Saccaka. And the result was that he became a follower of the
Buddha.20 Another
reference is recorded in the Abhayrajakumara
Sutta of the Majjhima Nikaya21
to the effect that Abhayarajakumara was sent by Nigantha Nataputta to
ask a question from the Buddha about his speech, as to whether the Tatha.
gata utters unpleasant words and is unkind to others. The
statement that "Abhaya was sent by Nigantha Nataputta" is not
supported by Jaina literature. Whatever its reason, the fact is evident
that the Jainas participated actively in discussions and tried to
indicate the defects of others religious utterence made about the future
of Devadatta. Abhaya then went to inquire as to how far he was correct
in his view. He does not appear to have questioned merely with the idea
of imputing faults to his opponent's theory. This seems to be the first
and most fundamental principle of Jaina conception of logical
discussions of that period. The propositional question put by Abhaya
Rajakumara to the Buddha is as follows: (i)
Would the Buddha make statements which are displeasing and unpleasant to
others? (bhaseyya nu kho......Tathagato
tam vacam ya sa vaca paresam appiya amanapa). (ii)
If so, how is he different from the ordinary individual who also makes
statements which are displeasing and unpleasant to others? (atha
kincarahi......puthujjanena nakaranam, puthujjano pi hi tam vacam
bhaseyya, ya sa vaca paresam appiya amanapa). (iii)
The Buddha would not make statements which are displeasing and
unpleasant to others (na
Tathagato tam vacam bhasati ya sa vaca paresam appiya): (iv)
Then why has he pronounced about Devadatta that he is doomed to
hell......that he is incorrigible (atha
kincarahi.....Devadatto byakato: a payiko Devadatto vyakato; apayiko
Devadatta atekicco Devadatto)? Here
Abhaya tried to show that the Buddha made a self-contradictory
statement. Likewise, Asibandhakaputta
Gamani22 a follower of Nigantha Nataputta made the following remarks
about the Buddha as he understood him: (i)
The Buddha in various ways speaks showing compassion to people (Bhagava
anekapariyayena kulanam anuddayam vanneti). (ii)
The Buddha during a famine......goes about with a large number of
disciples and behaves in a way detrimental to the interest of people (Bhagava
dubbhikkhe......mahata bhikkusanghena saddhim carikam carati, ucchedaya
Bhagava kulanam patipanno). The
questions asked by Abhaya Rajakumara and Asibandhakaputta Gamani are
based on such type of framed questions: If he qestioned thus and he
answers thus, we shall join issue (vadam) with him thus."23 They
are called "dupadam penham
or "ubhayatokotikam
panham" (dilemmas)24 As a matter of fact, these are the
conditional questions, which would have been thought out or taught
before embarking on a dispute. The
Jaina attitude to these debates and discussions was that they were meant
only to investigate the real defects in opponents theories. There were
not allowed to gain a victory through evil means, like quibbling,
analogues, power and so on. That is why Vitanda
is considered Vitandabhasa in
Jainism.25 The Buddha himself appreciates the attitude of such Panditas
and agrees with them on other matters.26 He called them Vinnu
or intelligent persons who are supposed to be hypothetical rational
critics.27 They used to make an impartial and intelligent assessment of
the relative worth of conflicting theories.28 On the basis of the above
view the later Jaina philosophers established the definition and means
of debates. Akalanka is perhaps the first to point out clearly such
definitions. He says that if one is capable of establishing his own view
(paksa) through right
devices, it is Jaya (victory)
for him and Parajaya (defeat
for the other.29 The
Buddhist philosohical literature which developed later, has not
mentioned any discussions and refutations of Jaina conception in this
connection. This may be due to the fact that both philosophies had
similar rules and regulations regarding such dabates, except for a few
differences (especially in the case of Nigrahasthanas). Evolution
of Epistemology Epistemology
and Logic are mainly concerned with the validity of knowledge and have
been subjects of controversy among philosophers from time immemorial. The
Buddha classified such thinkers into three groups in a Sutta of the Majjhima
Nikaya. It is said there that a Brahmana student went to ask the
Buddha "in which category he stands". The Buddha replied
"there are some recluses and Brahamanas who profess their doctrines
after finding a final and ultimate insight (ditthadhammabhin
navosonaparamippatta) into this life. "where does the venerable
Gorama stand among them?" The Buddha replied "I say that there
is a distinction among those who profess their doctrines after finding a
final and ultimate insight in this life. There are some recluses and
Brahmanas who are traditionalists (anussavika),
who profess their doctrines after finding a final and ultimate insight
in this life, such as the Brahmanas of the three Vedas (tevijja).
There are also some recluses and Brahamanas who profess their doctrines
after finding a final and ultimate insight in this life on mere faith
alone (kevalam saddha mattakena)
such as the reasoners (takki)
and metaphysicians (vimamsi,
lit. speculators). There are some other recluses and Brahmanas who
profess their dogmas after finding a final and ultimate insight in this
life by assimilating a higher knowledge (ditthadhammabhinnavosanaparamippatta)
personally (samam Yeva) of a
doctrine (dhamam) among
doctrines not traditionally heard of before. Now I am one of those who
profess the basis of their doctrines after finding a final and ultimate
insight in this life by gaining a higher knowledge personally of a
doctrine among doctrines not traditionally heard of before"30. This
reference seeks to classify the pre-Buddhist and contemporary thinkers
into three groups: (i) the Traditionalists (anussavika),
who obtained knowledge on the basis of their scripture and interpreted
it according to them. The Brahmanas or the followers of the Vedas are
enumerated in this group. (ii) The Rationalists or Reasoners (takki)
who gained knowledge through reasons. Sceptics, and Materialists come
under this group, and (iii) Experientialists, who attained higher
knowledge on the basis of personal experience (Samam Yeva).
Jainas, Buddhists, and Ajivikas would fall into this category. Like
the Buddha, Nigantha Nataputta is said to have professed his doctrines
after finding a final and ultimate insight by gaining a higher knowledge
personally, not traditionally heard of before. That is why he emphasised
more on knowledge rather than belief. (Saddhaya
kho Gahapati jnanam yeva panitataram).31 It is reported that he
claimed to have perfect knowledge (sabbannu)
and vision (sabbadassabi).
This insight can be obtained after attaining Right Vision (Samyagdarsana),
Right-Knowledge (Samyagjnana),
and Right Conduct (Samyagcaritra).32
Right view in the seven principles (Jiva
or soul, Ajiva or matter, Asrava
or inflow of karmas, Bandha
or bondage of karmas, Samvara
or checking of karmas, Nirjara
or shedding of karmas, and Moksa
or complete liberation from karmas) is the Samyagdarsana,
which is the basis of Right knowledge (Samyagjnana).
Purification of the attitude is regarded as the sine
qua non of the purification of knowledge and conduct. While Darsanamoha
(delusion of vision) destroys, immediately after Right Vision and Right
Knowledge emerge. Then through Right Conduct one can attain the Perfect
knowledge, the so-called Kevalajnana
or Sarvajnatva in Jainism.33 Knowledge
and Vision (Jnana and Darsana) In
Jainism, knowledge and vision or jnana
and darsana or omniscience
are the result of penance (tapa) and contemplation (dhyana).33 That is
why Nataputta is called Jnanavadin
in the Anguttara Nikaya (aham
anantena nanena anantam lokam janam passam viharami).34 According
to Jaina literature, Jnana or
cetana (consciousness) also
called Upayoga, is the main
characteristic of soul in Jainology.35 This upayoga is of two kinds,
viz. sakara (determinate) and
anakara (indeterminate). The
former is called janana,
while the latter is darsana.
Sakara upayoga consists of five classes of knowledge, viz. Matjjnana
(sensitive knowledge), Srutajnana
(scriptural knowledge), Avadhi
jnana (visual knowledge), Manahparyaya
jnana (mental knowledge) and Kevalajnana
(perfect knowledge). Anakara
upayoga is divided into four classes, viz. Caksudarsanavarana
(non-obscuring), Acaksudarsanavarana
(non-ocular-obscuring), Avadhidarsanavarana
(visual-obscuring), and the Kevaladarsanavarana
(perfect-conation-obscuring). Consciousness develops into the two forms,
knowledge and vision (jnanakara
and Jneyakara).36 We can say
that jnana is determinate
knowledge (sakara jnana) and darsana
is indeterminate knowledge (anakara
jnana). This is the distinction between jnana
and darsana. According to the Prajnapana
Sutra also both upayoga
and pasyatta can be sakara
as well as anakara. Acarya
Kundakunda mentions the view of his predecessors that vision reveals the
self (ditthi appapayasayaceva).
Hence, he considers the problem from the empirical as well as the
transcendental standpoint37 and concludes that the soul and its
knowledge and vision are identical and hence each can reveal the self as
well as non-self. Virasena
considers reality as a complex of universal-cum-particular and says in
his commentary called Dhavala on the satkhandagama of Puspadanta that jnana
comprehends external meaning of the nature of reality, while darsana
is the comprehension of the true form of that nature.39 That means jnana
reveals the external reality while darsana intuits its internal
characteristics. Siddhasena Divakara defines vision (darsana) as an
apprehension of samanya and knowledge (jnana)
as an apprehension of visesa jam
samannaggahanam damsanameyam visesiyam nanam).40 By this time the
defination of darsana had
been developed to mean the apprehension of samanya of an entity. It
is clear that vision or darsana
was originally considered to be the revealer of self (atma-prakasaka).
That is the reason why matijnana,
srutajnana and the avadhijnana,
which reveal external nature of reality, can be wrong if they are viewed
from the wrong angle, whereas caksudarsana, acaksudarsana and
avadhidarsana, which come prior to them, are not so. If Visesa
(particular) had been considered as having a meaning of general
observation of an entity, the Samsaya
(doubt), viparayaya
(perversion), and the anadhyavasaya
(indecision) would have existed in its perception made earlier, and
darsana would have been divided, like janan,
into darsana-adarsana etc. This defect would not arise if we define
vision as a revealer of self. For, it always exists prior to, as well as
at the time of knowledge.41 This
idea was expressed in logical terms by Pujyapada Devanandi in his
Sarvartha Siddhi.42 No endeavours had been made upto that time to
consider darsana as a valid standard of knowledge (pramana). Whether it
should be regarded as pramana or not was the main problem for the
logicians. Abhayadeva Suri, a commentator on the Sanmati
Tarka, expressed his view that Darsana, like Jnana, could be pramana
(valid)43 while Manikyanandi and Vadideva Suri45 considered it as a Pramanabhasa
(falsely valid). It may be that Nirvikalpaka darsana of Buddhism and not
Darsana of Jainism was in their minds when darsana was declared a
pramanabhasa. Pali
literature makes reference to the fact that Nataputta possessed
"infinite knowledge and vision". The Jaina Agamas46 confirm
the ancient view and say janadi
passadi and "Janamane
pasamane". This indicates that the activities of both,
knowledge and vision in an object can take place together and reveal its
knowledge and vision simultaneously. In
the later period, some of the Svetambara Acaryas tried to explain this
original idealogy in a different way. They said that Jnana
and darsana were conscious
activities, and the two conscious activities could not occur
simultaneously. But there is a controversy among them with regard to the
case of one who is omniscient (Kevalin). Some stick to the Agamas, while
others do not and assert either that a Kevalin's Jnana
and darsana are simultaneous
or that they are mutually identical and have no separate identity.
Siddhasena Divakara and Jinabhadra are the exponents of these views.47 On
the other hand, the Digambara Acaryas unanimously hold that the jnana
and darsana of a kevalin
occur simultaneously Kundakunda, a great Digambara Acarya states that jnana
and darsana of a kevalin
occur simultaneously even as the light and heat of the sun occur
simultaneously.48 Umasvami49 and his follower Pujyapada Akalanka51,
Vidyananda52 ete. also support this view. Later,
for the first time in the Jaina logical tradition it is analysed that
knowledge and vision of an entity reveal its knowledge and vision
simultaneously. A further explanation is given that an entity has two
forms, viz. Universal and Particular. The former is the subject of
vision and the latter of knowledge. Here knowledge and vision become
separate. That is why perhaps Abhayadeva Suri accepted both as valid. Another
point may be noted here. The etymology of Pramana (pramiyate
yena tatpramanm) points out that jnana is the more important cause
of right knowledge (pramana)
since it is an attribute of soul. Sannikarsa
(contact of an organ of senses with its effect) and sense-organs cannot
be pramana.53 Akalanka made a great coutribution towards the development
of the definition of pramana. He maintains non-discrepancy (avisamvadin)
as a test of pramana which adds one more characteristic, namely, tht of anadhigatarthagrahi
(knowledge which is not cognised).54 Akalanka, therefore, recognised
only the validity of knowledge which is determinative (nirnayatmaka),
non-discrepancy (avisamvadin)
and useful in samvyavahara
(empirical stand-point). In this way, the savikalpakajnana
(conceptual knowledge), not the nirvikalpakajnana
(non-conceptual knowledge) is considered as perception. The concept that
nirvikalapaka jnana could be
regarded as perception is successfully refuted by Santaraksit in the Tattvasangraha. Classification
of Knowledge Jainism
classifies Knowledge in two wavs: (i) Canonical (Agamika),
and (ii) Philosophical Darsanika.
The five kinds of knowledge such as mati, sruta, avadhi, manahparyaya
and kevalajnana are based on the former, while pratyaksa
(direct knowledge) and paroksa
(indirect knowledge) are developments of the latter. The Pratyaksa
is defined as knowledge obtained by self without the assistance of an
external instrument.55 It
is only to the Jainas that "aksa" means "Soul."56
Thus Pratyaksa in Jaina
Agamika tradition does not mean empirical perception, i.e. Knowledge
obtained through sense organs. According to this definition the Avadhijnana
(visual knowledge), Manahparayaya
jnana (intuition of mental knowledge) and Kevaljnana
(pure and perfect knowledge) are comprised Pretyaksa,
and Matijnana (sensuous
knowledge) and Srutajnana
(scriptural Knowledge) in Paroksa.57 The
Jaina definition of pratyaksa
was quite different from those of other philosophical systems. According
to the latter, pratyaksa is aknowledge gained through sense organs. It
created a serious difficult for Jaina philosophers. The rivals began to
question their standpoint. Having examined the arguments, the later
Jaina philosophers accepted pratyaksa as the knowledge produced by the
sense-organs also. Jinabhadra and Akalanka designated it as samvyavaharika
pratyaksa (empirical perception), while the real pratyaksa of
agamika tradition was called paramarthika
pratyaksa (transcendental perception).58 Indriyapratyaksa
and manasapratyaksa accepted
by the Naiyayikas and Vaisesikas are included in the first category.
Thus matijnana, which was put
under paroksa in the Agamika tradition, came under the category of pratyaksa
in philpsophical tradition. Likewise smrti, sanjna, Cinta and abhnibodha,
which were synonymous with mati
in the Agamic tradition59 are synonymous with smarana,
pratyabhjnana, tarka, and anumana
in the philosophical tradition. Therefore paroksa
pramana, are five including sruta (agama). Pratyaksa
Pramana or (direct knowledge) As
we have already observed Pratyaksa in Jainism is accepted as
self-cognition. Umasvami60 presented this definition in the Tattvarthasutra.
Samantabhadra.61 defined it as knowledge which is of self-revealing
charactar. Siddhasena Divakara in his Pramana Mimamsa added to it one
more characteristic, namely, "Badhavarjit"
(admitting of no contradiction). Akalanka
developed the theory further by adding avisamvadi
(non-discrepancy) and andhigatarthagrahi
(knowledge of object which is not yet cognised) as characteristics of
the validity of knowledge.62 This definition could remove several inner
contradictions of the earlier definitions. There
are four sub-divisions of matijnana, viz avagraha
(perception), iha
(speculation), avaya
(perceptual judgment) and dharana
(retention)63. They
are dependent of their pre-knowlede, but the emerge from sense-organs
and acknowledge the modes of a particular object. It is, therefore,
considered Samvyavaharika
pratyaksa.64
Except Carvaka, all other systems65 have classified Janyapartyaksa
(generated perception) as (i) Laukika
(Empirical) and (2) Alaukika
(transcendental). The nature of these perceptions is the same as the
nature of Samvyavaharika and Parmarthika
Pratyaksa of Jainas. Yogipratyaksa
or Yogi-jnana of the
Sankhya-Yogas,66 Nyaya-vaisesikas67, and the Buddhists68, Atmajnana
of the Mimamsakas69, are synonymous with Transcendental perception (Parmarthika
or Alaukika Pratyaksa which
is the special competence of the soul visistatma
sakti). According to Santaraksita in the Taitvasangraha,
the Jainas70 called this knowledge name Yagi-pratyaksa
or Yog-aja-pratyaksa. The
philosophers are not agreed on the question whether transcendental
perception is determinate (Savikalpaka)
or indeterminate (nirvikalpaka)
or both determinate and indeterminate (ubhaya).
The Buddhist tradition71 regards it as being only indeterminate, (Kalpanapodham),
while the Nyaya Vaisesikas and Mimamsakas72 are of the view that it can
be either determinate or indeterminata. The
Jainas, on the other hand, like the Sankhyas, think that determinate (savikal
paka) is the only real perception73. Santaraksita74 refuted this
idea. He referred to the view of Sumati who considered the Aksaja
pratyaksa (sensory perception) as Samvyavaharika
praiyaksa and Yogi pratyaksa
(intuitive perception) as Parmarthika
pratyaksa. He also added that according to the Jainas the
determinate perception (savikalpaka
pratyaksa) is the real perception.75 Savikalpaka
pratyaksa or determinate perception Knowledge
(Jnana) and vision. (Darsana),
the two main characteristics of the soul which we had already discussed,
are also called Darsanopayoga
(indeterminate cognition) and Jnanopayoga
(determinate cognition).76 The former is called the Nirvikalpaka
while the latter is called Savikalpaka.77 Te
Agamika tradition accepts both Savikalpaka
and Nirvikalpaka as valid due
to spiritual considerations. According to the real standpoint in this
tradition, a man obtains Right knowledge, is right in his cognition and
a man who holds a wrong view (mithyadrsti),
is wrong in his cognition, while from a practical standpoint both views
are right. Therefore in the Agamika tradition, both Savikalpaka and
Nirvikalpaka are valid from relative stand-points. Acarya Umasvami
divided cognitions into right and wrong ones. The Avadhidarsana,
and Kevaldarsana are
indeterminate transcendental perception, while Avadhijnana,
Manahparyayajnana and Kevalajnana
are determinate (transcedental perception).78 However,
in the logical tradition the validity of pramana has been changed. To
refute the opponents views, specially those of the buddhists, the Jaina
Acaryas used in their respective definitions of pramana some words like nirnaya
(detrmination) or jnana with
a view to indicate that darsana
or determinate cognition, which stands for cognition of the general (samanya-upayoga)
falls outside the purview of these definitions.79 It
may be noted here that the Buddhist philosophy accepts only the nirvikalpaka
pratyaksa or indeterminate perception as valid knowledge. As regards
the definiton of perception there are two Buddhist traditions, one is
headed by Dinnaga who does not accept non-illusory (abhranta)
nature of perception, and the otber headed by Dharmakirti who does so.
Santraksita and his followers support the latter stating that
Sense-perception is free from conceptual contents and hence not
erroneous.80 We see a thing first; then realise its name. Thus the
determinate knowledge (savikalpaka
jnana) depends on indeterminate knowledge (nirvikalpaka
Jnana) and, therefore, only indeterminate knowledge is perception.81 In
connection with establishing his own view Santaraksita refuted the view
of Acarya Sumati. According
to Sumati, both nirvikalpaka
and savikalpaka pratyaksa
should be recognised as valid as the first reflects the general form of
a thing or, in other words, its existence as an indefinite thing, while
the second (savikalpaka)
reflects the special characteristic of an entity thus perceived.82 This
theory appears to be in conformity with the Jaina Agamika tradition, but
not with the Logical point of view. Abhayadeva, the commentator of the Sanmatitarka
also took up the same position83. As we have already seen, the process
of general perception commencing from avagraha (mere apprehension) and
ending with Dharana (retention) passes from the indeterminate (nirvikalpaka)
state of knowledge to determinate (savikalpaka).84 Kamalasila
has explained the view of Sumati that a thing is amenable to
non-conceptual perception in the form of mere observation, or purely sub
jective ideation.85 But the Jaina philosophy does not accept it. Jainism
asserts that a thing is perceived by Darsan
or cognition, not by Alocana or observation,86 The visesavasyakabhasya
criticises the view, viz. "kei
dihaloyanapubbaamoggaham venti" which means a thing can be
apprehended by a purely subjective ideation. In his commentatery
Hemacandra Maladharideva referred to a karika by Kumarila "asti
alocana jnanam prathamam nirvikalpakam" It is possible that the
commentator thought this view was that of Kumarila and it is also
probable that kamalsila misunderstood the view of Sumati. Kumarila,
a Mimamsaka philosopher, asserted two kinds of sense-perception.
According to him, non-conceptual perception is purely subjective
ideation as apprehending the "specific individuality of the
particular (alocana jnanam
nirvikalpakam vyaktisvalaksanam), and the conceptual perception (savikalpaka
pratyaksa) is the apprehension of the universal (samanyavisayam
tu savikalpakam).87 Acarya
Sumati does not agree with this definition. He question: is the thing
before the eyes of the observer apprehended purely by itself, as
characterised by its own form which is impossible anywhere else ? or is
it not so apprehended ? If kumarila answers: there is non-apprehension
of the thing in a form distinguished from other things, then Sumati
states that in this position either there would be apprehension of the
thing itself only, or there would be no perception of the thing at all.
He illustrated his theory by reference to the perception of a Jar. The
Jar should be either apprehended without having the form of others or it
should not be apprehended. There could be no escape from these
alternatives89. Kumarila's
view is based on the definition of perception given in the Jaiminiyasutra90.
It is refuted by all non-Mimamsaka philosophers, Vedic91 as well as
Buddhist92 and Sumati appears to be the first Jaina Acarya to join them
in refuting this view. Having
criticised the view of Kumarila, Sumati proceeds to criticise the view
of Buddhist Acaryas, especially, that of Santaraksita. As we have seen,
Santarksita, a follower of Dharmakirit, defines perception as knowledge
free from conceptual contents and not erroneous.93 He tires to prove his
theory by means of inference and establishes that the nirvikalpaka
pratyaksa (indeterminte preception) is the only real perception.
Santaraksita further clarifies his own view by citing examples. He says:
in case a thing has no particular form, it cannot be accepted as a
particular thing. For instance, the white house owing to different
charactristics cannot be mistaken for a cow. It is the same case with
the perception.94 Here
in this definition the kalpana
is the main figure which has been defined in various ways by Buddhist
Philosophers. Santaraksita defined it as visistavisayavabodhah
(knowledge of qualified object.) Sumati is said to be against this view.
He argues that a thing cannot be qualified without having a eonnection-with
the qualifications, as in the case of a stick (danda)
and the stick-holder (dandin). Hence the cognition which apprehends the
qualifications (visesata) is
conceptual (savikalpaka).95
He again draws our attention to this defect of self-contradiction in
this theory pointing out that if there is always the apprehension of the
things as distinguished from homogeneous (sajatiya)
and heterogeneous (vijatiya)
things, then the apprehension would becom determinate (savikalpaka) for
it can be conveyed "this is different". Otherwise how does it
apprehend the difference between things.96 Sumati
pointed out another defect in the Buddhist theory. He asserts that there
is no particular (vises a)
without a touch of the universal (Samanya).
It cannot be argued in his opinion that the universal or
"being" is not touched at all by the sense-perception at the
time of apprehension, because in this position the particular would be
devoid of existence and thus it could become characterless; and as such
could not be apprehended by sense-perception, because it would be devoid
of "being" and become like the sky-flower (akasakusuma).97
Thus Sumati is of the view that the particular is perceived with the
character of the universal. All
Jaina logicians have tried to refute the Buddhist theory of
sense-perception following in the footsteps of Sumati. Akalanka is the
main figure to raise the question in this respect. Adding the adjectives
anadhigatarthagrahin, arisamvadin,
and visada to the existing
definition of perception98 he established that the Nirvikalpaka
pratyksa gets transormed into the savikalpaka is the pramana.99
Later on most of the Jaina logicians such as Acarya prabhacandra,100
Anantavirya,101 Vadiraja, Vidyananda,102 imitated him and elaborated his
ideas to refute the opponent's views.102 Refutation
of the Jaina conception of savikalpaka Pratyaksa
by Santraksita The
Jaina conception of Savikalpaka
Pratyaksa has been refuted by the Buddhist philosophers.
Santaraksita, even having defined perception as lucid knowledge without
reflection (kalpana)
criticised the view of Sumati on the ground that an entity does not have
any particualr qualities by which it can be differentiated at the moment
of apprehension. He thus sought to assert that there is no particular
thing at all. But the particular characteristic of a thing is implicit
in his classification of the universal (Samanya) into two types, viz. (i)
distinguished by qualifications, and (ii) not distinguished by
qualifications. The first is Nirvikalpaka,
and next is Savikalpaka pratyksa
(conceptual-preception). The former is the real pratyaksa while the
latter is practical. On
this basis, Santaraksita presents two arguments to refute Sumati's
theory. The first is that an entity does not possess any characters by
which it can be differentiated. We see a thing first and then realise it
as a pot or any particular thing. When the thing is apprehended, the
nagation of all other things comes forth naturally. Hence, the
non-conceptual perception (nirvikalpaka
pratyaksa) in the specific form of colour, shape, etc. appears and
then there follows the conceptual content (vikalpatmaka
jnana) associated with the words it
is different.103 Here
the words do not lead to cognition. The reason behind this is that the
specific individuality (svalaksanavastutva)
itself is independent of the words. The perception generated by them
also should be deprived of the words. The words do not have any relation
with the meaning. In the absence of words a thing exists, and in the
absence of a thing we use the words, which are dependent on gestures and
intentions. There is, therefore, no possibility of words in the Nirvikalpaka
pratyaksa. The second argument which Santaraksita puts forth is that
in particular thing there should be no other characteristics except that
of the "Particular".104 Thus,
whatever cognition appears with regard to the "specific
individuality" of things it beyond the range of words and is hence
non-conceptual perception. In his opinion, the lucidity and
determination in the savikalpaka
pratyksa is not its own characteristic, but it really comes from nirvikalpaka
pratpaksa. After a moment of nirvikalpaka
pratyksa, the sarikalpaka
pratyaksa is generated and the ascertainment and lucidity of a thing
which comes from nirvikalpaka prataksa appears to be of savikalpaka
pratyaksa. In this manner savikalpaka
pratyaksa also determinates a thing and is called perception from a
practical viewpoint (vyavahara), but the real perception is only the
non-conceptual (nirvikalpaka)
perception. In
the above criticism Santaraksita's Main arguments are that the nirvikalpaka
pratyaksa is the real pratyaksa and a thing cannot be both universal
and particular. Both these arguments are met by the later Jaina Acaryas.
They say that the nirvikalpaka
jnana of the Buddhists is the formless perception which is not
capable of determinating the nature of a thing. Therofore, it is
determinate (Sakara) and
lucid (visada), and could be accepted as a pramana. It
appears that to refute the validity of the Veda, the Buddhist
philosophers denied the real relation between the words and their
meanings. All sorts of knowledge gernerated in connection with words
which are not supported by the nirvikalpaka,
are declared to be invalid. As a matter of fact Buddhism also acccepts Savikalpaka
Pratyaksa. In the Vibhanga.105
Knowledge (jnana) is divided into two types Cognitative (Savitakka)
and Non-cognitative (Avitakka).
Both these types are similar to Savikalpaka
and Nirvikalpaka Pratyksa. The
object of perception We
have mentioned earlier that the pratyksa is of two kinds, viz. Samvyavaharika
(knowledge obtained through the senses and mind) and Parmarthika
pratyaksa (knowledge obtained by the sould itself, without the help
of the senses and the mind). The object of perception is realted to both
types of perception. The
validity of Pramana in Jain
philosophy is based on the nature of things, It asserts that a reality
is a multitude of atoms and possesses a characteristic of being
substance-cum-mode (dravyaparyayatmakam).
The permanence-in-change is its common nature, Out of six substances the
jiva, dharma, adharma, akasa,
and Kala are said to be
perceived only by the omniscient who has the parmarthik
pratyaksa while the mundane souls perceive the objects of inference,
not of sense-generated perception. The rest pudgala dravya is a subject
to be perceived by mundane souls through sense-generated perception (indriyajanya
pratyaksa). Jainism
is absolutely realistic in nature. Each atom or reality, in its
conception is quite indestructible and independent and always changes
into different modes. This system is both natural and eternal. The whole
universe continues in this way. There is no need to postulate a
creator-god to explain the origin and evolution of the universe. In
connection with the examination of the external world, Santaraksita
refers to the view of Sumati, He says the atoms have two qualities,
General (Samanya) and
Particular (Visesa.) The
objects perceived by sense-organs possess the general character. These
objects are conglomerations of atoms which appear as an entity with a
shape and size. The true quality of atoms is known only by the
emancipated one who attained the paramarthika
Pratyaksa or Yogipratyaksa.106 This
conception is made more clear in the Syadvadamanjari.
It is said that atoms which are co-related generate paryayas. They have
infinite and continuous changes which depend on the types of contact or
relation with others. For instance, when the atoms of the soil come into
contact with each other, they become compact and with their becoming
compact produce a pot. This process does not come about due to external
pressure but is the result of an internal connection with each other.
Therefore Jaina philosophy does not assert the extra avayavidravyas. As
regards the existence of atoms, we have both, Pratyaksa
and Anumana. We see the atoms
in the form of a pot (ghata).
The atoms, that cannot be perceived by ordinary men due to their
minuteness, are perceived by the Yogins. By inference also the Jainas
try to prove the existence of atoms. The body itself is a mass of atoms
wherein they get combined by such forces as time and cause the gross
body107. This
conception of object of perception has been a subject of criticism,
especially with the Buddhist logicians. The Vijnanavada, an extreme form
of idealism which is propounded by the Sautrantika and Yogacara schools,
asserts that there is no causal (yadakaram
jnanm) world of external (reality. In its opinion reality is only
the Vijnana (idea). Thus
the Vijnanavada denies the
external world by denying the atoms. It says that the heap of atoms or a
single body cannot be said to be in the external world. Both the Pratyaksa
and Anumana are unable to
prove their existence because ordinary mortals have never seen atoms
even in a dream. As regards the Pratyaksa
of Yogi, it demands great faith. The Anumana also is not helpful in this
respect; Because for want of pratyaksa
of atoms now can we get at the hetu
(reason) and the sadhya (to
be proved). Nor does the external world consist of bodies. When the atom
itself could not be proved, how can we hope to prove a body which
consists of many atoms. It is thus nothing but only a superstition
caused by a hypothesis of vasana
due to avidya or
ignorance.108 Acarya
Santaraksita also denies the existence of atoms. He refutes the view of
Sumati stating that one object cannot have two qualities. Otherwise the
object also will be consideed as two. Another argument is raised that if
the two qualities are not defferent from each other, why do you say that
the special quality of the atoms is perceived by the emancipated only
?109 By denying the existence of two qualities in one object,
Santaraksita tries to refute the view of Sumati. The
above criticism is based on the Vijnanavada,
which asserts that there is no existence of the external world. We see
it only on account of the hypothesis of vasana.
This criticism is answered by Jaina philosophers in latter works.
Hemachandra tries to reply that the existence of the world cannot be
refused, since knowledge is the action (kriya)
in which the object is supposed to be directed. Without the external
object there can be no perception. Therefore, Jainism admits the
existence of both, the atoms and the body (avayavi). As
regards the criticism that the atoms of the body would be conflicting
with one another, Jaina philosophy admits this fact, but it tries to
solve this problem through Anekantavada.
As Hemachandra says, `criticism' of atoms, therefore, cannot affect
those who believe in Syadvada,110 according to which a body is one and
yet manifold. Paramarthika
Pratyaksa (Trancsendental Perception) The
Paramarthika Pratyaksa is the outcome of the destruction of Jnanavaranakarma
(knowledge obscuring karama). It springs forth from the purified soul
itself without the assistance of sense-organs or any other external
internal instruments. That is the reason why it is called the perfect
lucid perception (visada
pratyaksa). It is of two kinds: Sakala
pratyaksa (complete direct knowledge) Kevalajnana
(perfect knowledge or omniscience) comes under the former, and the Avadhijnana
(visual knowledge), Manahparyayajnana
(mental knowledge) under the latter. Avadhi
Jnana, as its name
indicates, is limited by dravya
(substance), Ksetra (place) Kala
(time) and bhava (emotion).
It is of three kinds--desavadhi
(partial visual knowledge), paramavadhi
(high visual knowledge), and sarvavadhi
(full visual knowledge). Viewed from another aspect it is divided into Bhavapratyaya
(birth-born visual knowledge) and gunapratyaya
(acquired by merit). The former is possessed by those in heaven and hell
by birth,111 while the latter can be secured by human beings as well as
five-sensed sub-human beings after destruction-cum-subsidence of the
relevant karmic veil (Ksayopasama-nimitta).112
Only the forms having shapes (rupin) can be known by avadhijnana.113
The formless, such as soul (jiva),
dharma (principle of motion),
adharma (principle of rest). akasa
(space), and Kala (time) are
not within its scope of perception. It can penet rate infinite, number
of cycles, both past and furure. Manahparyaya
jnana reveals the
thoughts of human beings. It is of two kinds, viz. rjumati
(simple direct or mental knowledge) and vipulamati
(complex direct or mental knowledge). Umasvami distinguishes them on the
ground that the latter is purer and everlasting, while the former has
less purity and infallibility.114 Pujyapada,115 and Akalanka116 support
his view. But Jinabhadra is of somewhat different view viz. that manahparyaya
jnana knows the states of mind directly by intuition, but the
external objects thought of by the mind can be inferred.117 Later
Acaryas followed both these views. Umasvami
makes a distinction between avadhi
and manahparyaya. He says
that (i) the former is less pure than the latter, (ii) the former can
extend to the whole universe, while the latter is limited to the centre
of the middle world. (iii) The first can be secured by all beings
possessed of mind; while the other only by saints bhaving supernatural
powers, and (iv) the subject matter of the first is gross, while that of
the latter is very subtle. But Siddhasena Divakara does not recognise
any distinction between avadhi
and manahparyaya, since
"subhuman organisms possessed of two or more sense-organs are also
found to strive by means of attraction and repulsion, and thus are
possessed of minds and as such it will be proper to extend the scope of
manahparyaya to the minds or the objects of the minds of them as well,
or otherwise it will be improper to postulate manahparyay as a separate
category of knowledge.118 It can however, be considered a specific type
of Avadhijnana. Kevalajnana
is perfect knowledge of all substance and their modifications. It is
generated after complete destruction of the veil of the Mohaniya
karma (delusing) which is the most powerful in the Karmic mater.
Hence the soul comes to perceive all things past, present and future.
When a person achieves perfect knowledge, he is called Omniscient. According
to Jainism, no one can be a teacher (Tirthankara) without being
omniscient. This perfect knowledge can be obtained by the purified soul
which has consiousness (cetana
or upayoga) as its sole
characteristic.119 The term Upayoga
is used to denote the darsana the jnana which are the main features of
the soul. Darsana is
perception and jnana is
knowledge.120 Soul, its knowledge, and its intution all these are
identical and hence each can reveal the self as well as nonself.121
Akalanka is of the view that when the soul cognises the object, it is
called Jnana; and when the
soul perceives itself, it is called Darsana.122 It
is apparent now that at the destruction of Jnanavarana,
Darsanavarana; Mohaniya, and Antaraya,
the soul obtains inner illumination and becomes omniscient. According
to Jaina philosophy, each and every entity is somehow related to all
other entities in the univers. Such relations are called modes or
paryayas of the entity. If one knows an entity completely, these modes
will also be known completely. That is why it is said that one who knows
one, knows all, and one who knows all, knows one. In the Pravacanasara,
Kunda-kunda saya: One who does not know simultaneously the realities of
past, present and future, and the three worlds, cannot know even a
single object with its fnfinite modifications, if one does not know all
objects, how will he be able to know one ? For instance, if one is
inclined to have a knowledge of ghata, he should have knowledge of its
intrinsic nature as well as ghata itself, since knowledge reveals all
the objects. As the soul has infinite capacity to know all the objects,
when one attains such power, he has to know all the objects.124 severe
penance with Right vision, Right knowledge, and Right conduct is
required to attain such purified stage of soul. The
early Pali Canon as well as the latter Buddhist philosophical literature
criticised the view of Jainas that their Tirthankaras were omniscient.
In the Majjhima Nikaya the
Buddha says to Sandka Paribrajaka that "Some teacher, all-knowing (sabbanna),
all seeing (sabbadassavi)
claims all-embracing knowlledge and vision (apariseam
nanadassanam), Saying whether I am walking or standing still or
sleep or awake, knowledge and vision are constanly and perpetually (satatam
samitam) before me." Further the Buddha says, "he enters
an empty place, and he does not receive alms and a dog bites him, and he
encounters a fierce elephant, and he encounters a fierce horse, and he
encounters a fierce bullock, and he asks a woman and man their name and
clan, and he asks the name of a village or market town and the
way". So if any one asks him why he need question in this manner if
he is omniscient, then he replies this: "I had to enter an empty
place, therefore I entered.125" At
another place the buddha says to Mahanama that he had seen the Niganthas
performing severe penance at rajagaha on the Isigili kalasila. He then
asked them "why do you people do so ? They replied that the
Nigantha Nataputta was omniscient and he had said that by severe penance
all past deeds would be destroyed and the new deeds would be prevented.
In this way, they would attain salvation. then the Buddha asked them
"Do all of you know the past and the future of yourselves and your
deeds. He went on to say "You do not know whether you did an evil
deed like this or that. You do not know the getting rid of unskilled
states of mind, the uprising of skilled states." Getting the reply
"no" from them the Budha remarked "these beings, revered
Niganthas, do those who are born again among men in the world, and are
wrathful (luddha), blood
handed (lohitapanino),
dealing in cruelty (kururakammanta)
do these go forth among the Naganthas."126 Likewise Udayi
Paribrajaka says to Gotama the all-knowing omniscient (Nigantha
Nataputta), on being asked a question by me concering the past, shelved
the question by asking another, answered off the point and evinced
temper and ill-will and sulkiness, (purimani,
bhante, divasani purimatarani, sabbnnu sabbadassavi......so maya
pubbantam arabbha panham puttho samano annenannam paticari, bahirddah
katham apanamesi, kopam ca dosam ca appaccayam ca patvakasi).127 The
Dhammapada Atthakatha
presents a very interesting story regarding the dialogues that took
place between Sirigutta and Garahadinna, the followers of the Buddha and
the Nigantha Nataputta respectively. Garahadinna, a follower of the
Nigantha Nataputta said to Sirigutta that the Niganthas are omniscient;
they know the past, present and future. Afterwards, Sirigutta, a
follower of the Buddha decided to try the boastful claim of the naked
ascetics (Niganthas). He got
a ditch dug between two houses and had it covered. Niganthas were then
invited to alms. When the Niganthas came, they fell into the pit and
their bodies were covered with mud and filth. Then it is said that he
had beaten them with sticks and brought humiliation upon them. After a
similar trial he proved that Buddhist monks were omniscient.128 It may
be noted here that all the Niganthas are not said to be omniscient, but
only a very few who could attain the perfect knowledge after performing
the required duties. This story, however, refers to the Jaina tradition
that its Tirthankaras and some prominent monks were omniscient.129 Likewise,
later Buddhist philosophical literature also referred critically to the
Jaina conception of omniscience or Kevalajnana.
Dharmakirti, in the course of establishing the "Dharmajnatva"
in the Buddha, points out the superfluity of Jaina view of omniscience
and says that the anusthanagatajnana
(a knowledge that has a bearing on life or practice is more importast,
than having a knowledge of the number of bacteria (kitasankhya),
which is of no use at all for human beings. The real tattvadrasta
(knower of scripture) in the opinion of Dharmakirti is one who knows
what is to be abandoned and what is to be accepted and not everything.
It is immaterial whether one knows everything or not, but what matters
is whether he knows the essentaial thing, that is what he ought to know.
If the mere range of knowledge was valuable in itself, without its
bearing on life, why not worship vultures who soar in to the atmosphere
and thereby get a long range of sight.130 Thus he asserts the view that
a absolute purity in life and not unlimited knowledge is the essential
characteristic of a Teacher. Prajnakaragupta,
the commentater of Dharmakirti also supports Dharmakirti's view, but he
goes one step further and establishes the omniscience of the Buddha. He
also says that it can be attained by any spiritual aspirant, who masters
the art of subduing passions.131 Thus
it is only for the sake of argument that this conception of omniscience
had been recorded in the Pali Canon as well as in later Buddhist
philosophical literature, since no Jain view regarding this problem is
correctly and completely mentioned. It was therefore not possible to
give an accurate picture of the Jaina theory of omniscience. This much,
however, we can say that the conception of omniscience in Jaina
Tirthankaras is not a new one. It might belong to Parsvanatha or the
period prior to that tradition, since the Niganthas, who the Buddha saw
performing severe penance on Risigiri Kalasila at Rajagaha would be the
followers of Parsvanatha or an earlier tradition. The
whole Jaina literature seeks to establish the fact that Jaina
Tirthankaras are omniscient, while denying the omniscience of any other.
The Bhagavati Sutra (9.32)
says that the Nirgranthas who belonged to the Parsvanatha tradition did
not accept the Nigantha Nataputta as a porphet or head of a Jaina sect
unless it was proved that he was all-knowing and all-seeing.132 Later
* caryas such as Kundakunda, Samantabhadra, Akalanka, Vidyananda try to
establish omniscience on the basis of inference. We have already
mentioned Kundakunda argument in this connection. Then Samantabhadra
says that there are three kinds of entities, viz. the subtle (suhsma),
proximate (antarita), and
remote (duravarti). They must
be perceived simulataneously by somebody, since all objects are to be
perceived. Hence there must be some one omniscient.134 Virasena
presents another argument in support of omniscience. He says that Kevalajnana
(omniscience) is innate in the soul. Due to destruction-cum-subsidence
of karmas, it functions as matijnana.
The self-cognised mati implies the fractional kevala jnana, just as the
observation of a part of a mountain leads us to the perception of the
mountain itself.135 The
Jaina philosophers did not emphasise Dharma
jnatva like Dharmakirti or early Buddhist tradition, but they
endeavoured to point out that a person is omniscient when he is both Dharmajna
as well as Sarvajna, because
Dharma jnatva depends on sarvajnatva. Akalanka
presents another argument which is also referred to by Dharmottara, a
Buddhist philosopher in the Dharmottara-pradipa.136
His argument is that if we deny supersensorial knowledge, how can
astrological divinations be made ? Hence, it must be accepted that there
is a faculty of super-sensorial knowledge which is nothing but Kevalajnana
or omniscience.137 After
the destruction of the evil of karmic bondage one can attain the
inherent capacity of his own soul, and perceive all things.138 They very
progressive gradation of knowledge implies the highest magnitude of
knowledge attained by man. If one has no capacity to know or perceie all
things at once he will not be able to do so even by means of the
Veda.139 Hence we have to accept that one can become omnisceint.
Impossibility of omniscience cannot be established unless one has
knowledge of persons of all times. Consequently, one who rejects
omniscience for all times must himself be omui scient.140 Presenting the
positive arguments in this way, Akalanka relies on the negative
arguments that there is no contradictory pramana141
to reject the established omniscience and therefore it is certain. He
then substantiates this argument by examining the various so-called
contradictory pramanas.143 Dharmakirti
and his commentator, Prajnakargupta, think that the Jaina conception of
omniscience cannot be accepted for want of Sadhaka-badhakapramana145
(assisting and contradicting evidence). Akalanka replies this criticism
by saying that one cannot establish the non-existence of omniscience
without being omniscient. He further says that there is no badhaka
pramana to refute omniscience in Jainism, and the absence of badhaka
pramana is itself a sadhakapramana.145 As
regards Anusthanagatajnana
urged by Dharmakirti. Vadiraja, a commentator of Akalanka, questions
"By which pramanas does the Buddha perceive the Anustheyagatavastu
? Neither can Pratyaksa
Pramana be helpful in this respect, otherwise what will be the use
of Anusthana ? Nor will be Anumana
(inference) pramana will
solve our problem, because it depends on the pratyaksa. Thus the Anustheyagata
Jnana in itself has no importance.143 So
far as Kitasankhya-parijnana
and its purusathopayoga are
concerned, he says that it is essential to include Kitasankhya-parijnana
as an integral part of omniscience, as caturaryasatya
implies the Duhkhasatya of
creatures living around. If the Buddha has not grasped the Caturaryavedanatva,
how could he preach to his disciples convincingly? He then remarks that
if the Kitasankhya-parijnana
serves no useful purpose, what then is the use of Bhiksu-sankhya-parijnana
in Buddhism.146 ? Thus
the Jainas established the theory of omniscience, whereas the Buddhist
refuted it in Nigantha Nataputta. According to Jainism its adherents
could aspire to be omniscient. But it was only Nigantha Nataputta who
attained this spiritual height at that time. However, the masses
considered all Niganthas to be omniscient, because some of them gained
various powers of insight. The Buddha, apparently under the impression
that this was the actual claim of Jainism, criticised it. The later
Buddhist philosophers also followed him. Latern, on the imitation of
Jainism, the Buddha is also made an omniscient in Buddhist
Literature.147 |